Saturday, February 15, 2025

Subjectivity and vanity in Hegel's philosophy (Part 5)

  Pathologies of moral subjectivism

Without any objective system of duties and rights arbitrary subjectivity remains the only principle available to determine the content of the good. It is especially "hairsplitting reflection" (spitzfindige Reflexion) that places extreme emphasis on exceptional situations, for example when duties collide, perhaps in order to untie itself from rights and duties altogether.[1] But exceptional situations that come about only seldom in reality cannot totally expunge universal principles and duties,[2] under which particular cases are to be subsumed[3]—nevertheless, “[m]en often say, their conscience advised them this or that, in order to evade a reproach[4]

Groundless and conscientious actions

If formal conscience were to make a final decision regarding a collision between duties, such a decision would eventually be groundless,[5] since “[a] ground should be something objective, universal”[6], therefore independent of conviction, which is contingent and encumbered with the possibility of error; without education (Bildung) or discipline (Zucht) of the particular will, one could argue about anything on the basis of such subjective grounds.[7] On the other hand, it is through discipline that the subject is expected to relinquish its particular authority with regard to the authority, say, of the state, which is a more universal authority,[8] and act in favour of a higher—not self-made, but solid and objectively recognized—duty;[9]a conscientious person is one who does her duties, not one who first makes them[10].

Forming a separate idea of the good

We may ask ourselves: Why is such a formal and one-sided conscience that discards objectivity[11] deemed problematic? Hegel’s handwritten notes to Rechtsphilosophie provide significant insight into the matter: beyond the finite horizon of the—allegedly absolute—formal conscience are other subjects, with their respective expectations and particular ends—a whole society even. 

If people were to conform their actions solely to what resides in their particular conscience, that is, distinct from principles of right or even opposed to what is objectively recognized as right and ethical (sittlich), then no assurance (Versicherung) or trust (Zutrauen) that their actions are seriously meant could be provided:[12]If everything were left to the decision of conscience, then objectivity would dissolve”.[13] Lacking in content, subjectivity would then come to decide by itself what is obligatory based on the satisfaction of its own conviction and good reasons (aus guten Gründen),[14] thus forming its separate idea of the good.[15]

 

Jean-Georges Vibert, The committee on moral books, 1866
Jean-Georges Vibert, The committee on moral books, 1866


[1] See Hegel, Die „Rechtsphilosophie“ von 1820 mit Hegels Vorlesungsnotizen 1821–1825, § 137, 485. [My own translation]. Cf. Die Philosophie des Rechts (1821/22), Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 2005, § 137, 134.

[2] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 134.

[3] See Hegel, Philosophie des Rechts nach der Vorlesungsnachschrift von H. G. Hotho 1822/23, Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, frommann-holzboog, 1974, § 137, 428.

[4] Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 133. [My own translation].

[5] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts. Die Mitschriften Wannenmann (Heidelberg 1817/18) und Homeyer (Berlin 1818/19), § 62A, 83.

[6] Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 132, 130.

[7] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 132, 130–131.

[8] See Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 132, 131.

[9] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 133. Cf. Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 13, 134.

[10] Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 133. Cf.  Philosophie des Rechts 1822/23, § 137, 428. [My own translation]

[11] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 136.

[12] See Hegel, Die „Rechtsphilosophie“ von 1820 mit Hegels Vorlesungsnotizen 1821–1825, § 137, 487. Cf. Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, §140, 142.

[13] Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts. Die Mitschriften Wannenmann (Heidelberg 1817/18) und Homeyer (Berlin 1818/19), § 70 Anmerkung, 246. [My own translation]

[14] See Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, in Werke vol. 7, E. Moldenhauer, K. M. Michel (eds.), Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp,  § 132 Anmerkung, 246; Elements of the Philosophy of Right, tr. by H. B. Nisbet, Cambridge University Press, 159.

[15] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 132, 130. Cf. Philosophie des Rechts nach der Vorlesungsnachschrift von K. G. v. Griesheims 1824/25 (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog, 1974), § 137, 363.

Tuesday, December 31, 2024

Subjectivity and vanity in Hegel's philosophy (Part 4)

 True and formal conscience

A certain difference between subjective cognizance of the value of an action and objectivity has been made apparent in Hegel's account of morality, and develops further as follows: 

  • When conscience acts according to objective determinations and obligations—which only ethical life (Sittlichkeit) can provide to subjective knowledge—it is thus called true conscience (wahrhaftes Gewissen). True conscience consists in “the disposition to will what is good in and for itself[1] and acts according to objective duties,[2] insofar as it relinquishes the possibility of determining the particular content of the good itself.[3]

  • If the actions of conscience do not conform to any fixed principles (feste Grundsätze), conscience retains only “the formal aspect of the activity of the will”[4]. Within the standpoint of morality the only available content for conscience to adopt appears to be “the infinite formal certainty of itself[5].

Universality contra self-certainty

Obviously, this content may or may not be in accordance with what is “truly right and duty”[6]. As Hegel mentions, “rationality in and for itself”[7] is not to be treated as equivalent to what a certain individual holds to be right and true; in fact, the content of this supposed good (Gutseinsollenden) must be compared with “universal determinations of thought” that take “the form of laws and principles[8]

On the contrary, formal conscience improperly presumes that its self-certainty and inwardness constitute the only guiding principle to determine the good and evaluate its actions—as if such an arbitrary positing of the good were isolated from objective determinations.[9] Of course, this once more indicates a stance of total divergence of the subject from what is acknowledged as objectively and universally valid.

The limits of moral standpoint

To the degree that conscience holds fast to this one-sided (moral) standpoint, the state cannot recognize it as valid “any more than science can grant any validity to subjective opinion, assertion and the appeal to subjective opinion”[10]. Conscience is entitled to know what the good in and for itself is, and thus to acknowledge as obligatory only what it cognizes as the good, provided that this cognizance aligns with what is truly right and rational—this takes the form of universal determinations based on thought. But conscience is not entitled to posit itself the content of the good, unless it clings on to its self-certainty and subjective opinion.[11]

 

Franz Marc - Kämpfende Formen
Franz Marc - Kämpfende Formen, 1914


[1] Hegel, Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, in Werke vol. 7, E. Moldenhauer, K. M. Michel (eds.), Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp § 137, 254; Elements, 164.

[2] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts. Die Mitschriften Wannenmann (Heidelberg 1817/18) und Homeyer (Berlin 1818/19), § 66 Anmerkung, 87. Cf. Philosophie des Rechts nach der Vorlesungsnachschrift von H. G. Hotho 1822/23Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt, frommann-holzboog, 1974, § 137, 427–428.

[3] See Hegel, Die Philosophie des Rechts  (1821/22), Frankfurt am Main, Suhrkamp, 2005, § 137, 133.

[4] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137, 254; Elements, 164.       

[5] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137, 255; Elements, 164.

[6] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137 Anmerkung, 255; Elements, 164.

[7] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137 Anmerkung, 255; Elements, 164. 

[8] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137 Anmerkung, 255; Elements, 164–165. Cf. Philosophie des Rechts nach der Vorlesungsnachschrift von K. G. v. Griesheims 1824/25 (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: frommann-holzboog, 1974), § 137, 362.

[9] See Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 137, 132.

[10] Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137 Anmerkung, 255; Elements, 165.

[11] See Hegel, Grundlinien, § 137 Anmerkung, 256; Elements, 165. Cf. Die Philosophie des Rechts 1821/22, § 132, 129–130.